complex systems phenomena of critical slowing down, and flickering

Hi Felix,

On Feb 20, 2016, at 8:00 AM, Fel Reb <rebfel@gmail.com> wrote:

I don't have access to respond to the posthaven blog, so I'm sending it directly to you....

Your questions made me think of meta-stability and Simondon... I don't know if if I'm off in left field but here are my two cents' worth... Gotta say though that f is not just any (differentiable) scalar function… it's a nice way at "inducing" continuity where the underlying may not have it..

Yes, right — in fact distribution theory : representing a function by convolving against approximations to the identity with a kernel that converges to the Dirac delta function is a well known and beautiful way to densely approximate any integrable function — a much vaster set of functions, which includes wildly non-differentiable and even discontinuous functions — by infinitely differentiable functions.

If the second time-derivative is going to zero, one would be approaching a steady state of no change, i.e. no new energy entering or leaving the system.

The second time-derivative of what, prices of Apple stock, immigrant flows through Ellis Island ?  That is only the case when we’re talking about position (potential energy mass * dx).   

If the second time-derivative is positive, why would that induce flickering? If the second derivative is positive at a point, are not you not only providing half the story? Wouldn’t you need to see how the change is changing over time rather than tending? 

Yes exactly, that’s why I speak of second time-derivative f’’: change is f’  and change of change is f’’.

If the potential is locally a quadratic with nonzero second derivative, then it looks like a parabola (in potential space).   The classic dynamic (solution) subject to that sort of potential (differential equation) is harmonic oscillation. 


For the thing to flicker, one would need discontinuities in the system or very tight oscillations to the changing system... tending-positive to infinity, finding another “plateau” of zero (or near zero) and then another tending-negative to infinity and repeat
This flickering effect feels like a cycling of meta-stability where contributing factors within the system impede the system from acquiring a one way or the other... or exit that meta-stable state... the correlation lengths would depend on the energy dynamics of the system, how rough the cycling is, i.e. how much energy is required to get out of the troughs of the meta-stability yet not enough to break away from the cycling and revert to the meta-stable trough. Experimentally, to break the spell one needs to introduce ever larger amounts of energy, heighten the amplitude of the energy dynamics as roughness into the cycling so one overwhelms the threshold boundary and break free from the prevalent dynamic onto another regime. You gotta introduce some rough stuff into the system, i.e. introduce difference or change, to mix it up and break free from the toxic stability....

Does this make sense?

Not clear what you mean by all this.  Are we speaking of the base space, or the state space of configurations, or the space of potential energy (functional on configurations)?

I hope this doesn’t land like a hair in the soup, like they say in Qc French.

hahaha , what’s that in quebecois?

Best, Felix

P.S. I found this reference on my way to somewhere else... thought it might be an interesting comment to the death scenario of the . 

From Nature

Universal resilience patterns in complex networks

Jianxi Gao, Baruch Barzel & Albert-László Barabási

Nature 530, 307–312 (18 February 2016) doi:10.1038/nature16948

Received 13 July 2015 Accepted 14 December 2015 Published online 17 February 2016

Félix


Félix Rebolledo

Email: rebfel@gmail.com

Fone: 51 9110 9920

View the post and reply »

Synthesis: complex systems phenomena of critical slowing down, and flickering

Brandon, Chris R, Josh Connor,

Marten Scheffer gave a keynote at the Complexity conference last Fall about critical slowing down  phenomenon indicating tipping points.   Flickering  is a different signature.   We had a good conversation about our ECS and Synthesis.   ( He’s also quite into the sound scene and dabbled in sonification early in his career. )   We should contact him as well as Alex Penn for our ECS workshop, maybe Skype? 

Maybe here’s how we can think of both phenomena: Consider a model  R x M where   R is the single time dimension and M are the non-temporal dimensions of the model.    Let  f: R1 x M —> R1 be any (differentiable) scalar function.

Look at the partial derivatives of f.   Maybe if the second time-derivative  is close to 0 we get the phenomenon of critical slowing down.   But if the second time derivative is positive we get flickering.   Correlation lengths depend on the partial derivatives w/r to M

Is this correct?
Xin Wei

Flickering gives early warning signals of a critical transition to a eutrophic lake state


 

  1. Dearing, J. A., Braimoh, A. K., Reenberg, A., Turner, B. L. & van der Leeuw, S. Complex land systems: the need for long time perspectives to assess their future. Ecol. Soc. 15, 21(2010)
  2. Dearing, J. A. et al. Extending the timescale and range of ecosystem services through paleoenvironmental analyses: the example of the lower Yangtze basin. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 109, E1111–E1120 (2012)

Synthesis: psychology, neuroscience, Helga Wild, Karl Pribram, Helgi-Jon Schweitzer

Dr. Helga Wild’s earlier research in neuroscience and psychology was with:

Prof. Helgi-Jon Schweitzer @ Innsbruck
Prolegomena zur Theoretischen Grundlegung der Psychologie Kurzer Einführender Text. 
Erscheinungsjahr: 2002

Prof. Karl Pribram @ Stanford
Brain and Perception: Holonomy and Structure in Figural Processing

Xin Wei

Fernando Zalamea: Mathematics is Metaphysics (2015)

Mathematics is Metaphysics

World philosophy has been stuck for decades in a scientific vision that cannot explain reality any more.   Thus to get beyond Kant and reawaken thought and culture.

Fernando Zalamea

I propose here a pamphlet in favor of a synthetic thought at the beginning of the 21c — “a pamphlet [opuscolo] with an aggressive character” according to a celebrated dictionary — implying a combat with light weapons but for assault; the thought implicates every form of intersection between sciences, arts, philosophy, essay, critique, and struggles systematically against stagnant and tired compartments; the synthesis counterposes analyses, according to well defined polarities: compositions and decompositions, relations versus elements, exterior versus interior, impurity versus sterilization, (mathematical) category versus set theory; the 21c invites us to a reflection on our contemporary intellectual spirit [spettro].  In the 20c, there was such a strong influence (in some moments brilliant, in others deplorable) of the analytic linguistic turn that it is now time to formulate a counter-proposal for a new non-dogmatic opening of thought.

Giancarlo Rota underlined in many polemical articles the existence of a “perilous influence of mathematics on philosophy.”   The expression refers to the influence of a restricted mathematical logic (classical first order logic) and a fundamentalist perspective (Cantorian set theory) that, taken too seriously by philosophers, uncritically gave space to a certain “hard” analytic philosophy, guided by logical and linguistic considerations with which — so it was thought — one could eliminate metaphysical digression [divagazione] or phenomenological or aesthetic imprecision.  All in all, that expression was in its time ironic and paradoxical because the real mathematics (of figures such as Galois, Riemann, Hilbert or Grothendieck, from the middle of the 19c to the end of the 20c) developed without curing itself at all of the subtle logical and linguistic considerations of analytic philosophy.   In reality, there was indeed through a profound ignorance of the “real mathematics” of the beginning of the 20c (algebraic and analytic number theory, abstract algebra, topology, complex variables, functional analysis, etc.) and through an (un)conscious construction of myth that it was possible to attain the project of analytic philosophy, which was only apparently rooted in mathematical studies, whereas the real situation was completely opposite.

The multiple references to a supposed “Fregean revolution” in the foundations of mathematics at the beginning of the 20c showed a good example of this mythology which obstinately endured.  You ask yourselves, of any logic active in the beginning of the 20c in what consisted this supposed “Fregean revolution” you discover that treats a simply inexistent event, a myth created by “standard” philosophies and histories of logic.   In reality, it is well known that logic includes three fundamental branches (model theory, recursion, sets) of which the first, model theory, generated the major logical advances in the last decades (Shelah, Zilber, Hrushovskii), which had very clear ancestors (Peirce, Löwenheim, Tarski) and where Frege glittered by his absence.  Recursion theory began with Hilbert, Skolem, Gödel, and set theory with Cantor and Zermelo and, although in these two lines one could insert in part also Frege, certainly he could not compare (be regarded) as “precursor” much less as “revolutionary.”   Thus, in the development of mathematical logic, the special position of Frege constituted only a tenacious myth.  On the other hand, and more broadly, if one thinks of the development of real mathematics, the figure of Frege is entire out of the running.  In addition there is [Altra cosa è registrare] Frege’s central and essential impetus for Russell and for the development of analytic philosophy.   But this confirms only that “analytic philosophy” and “real mathematics” have always followed divergent paths.

Therefore we must explode the prime grand myth of analytic philosophy based on mathematics.   The “dangerous influence of mathematics on philosophy,” in Rota’s phrase [calembour], must be sharpened as the “dangerous influence of mathematical logic and Cantorian theory of sets on analytic philosophy.”  From the moment that mathematics is infinitely vaster than the pair classical logic + Cantorian sets, arises a new influence of real mathematics on philosophical thought.  Our concept in this article is summarized by suggesting that this influence is blossoming but, seeing as real mathematics is practically unknown, it has not arrived at the point of being “dangerous.”  It would be good if after some decades, a critic at the level of Rota could observe the “dangerous influence of topology, of complex variables, of logic of sheaves and category theory on philosophical thought.”   By then, however, the term “philosophy” will be discovered a new continent, a sort of “synthetic philosophy” and the spirit of mathematical, philosophical, and critical methodology (that) can be put in motion for opening new fields of thought.

Many great masters at the end of the 19c and the beginning of the 20c already profoundly explored the studies of the limits of contradiction (Peirce, Florenskij), and adopted a “geological critique” of art and culture (Warburg Benjamin, Auerbach).  In a sense of opening and of opposed similar [contrapposizione simile], it can be said that the Italian school was particularly attentive to the alternative, sia a partire starting from Peirce (with figures on world rank like Rosella Fabbrichesi and Giovanni Maddalena) sia a partire from Florenskij and Warburg.   It is true to say that in mathematics as in arts, the “two principal modes with which humanity thinks,” as Francastel said, the fundamental source of invention comes from a staircase of contradiction, obstruction, blind spots, a list that has taken place outside of analytic sterilization.  One of the prime objectives of which one must call “synthetic philosophy” consists of taking on board this network of shadows and boundaries forgotten by the “normal” currents of analytic philosophy.

The most important of the “shadows” in the history of philosophy, excluded with dubious pride from analytic philosophy, is doubtless Metaphysics.  This “other to Physics,” which is to say also the “other to language,” becomes for the fastidious analytic philosophers [analysts] tantamount to the contradiction “other to logic.”  However one recalls that the greatest advances in science and the arts, and therefore the most creative moments in history of humanity are found outside language and outside logic.  For philosophy to leave aside the conceptual study of a Riemann, a Mahler, a Monet, is an academically accepted barbarism, as if [analytic] philosophy wants to incestuously limit its own work to a primary, secondary, tertiary… n-ary discussion of self-contained philosophical systems.

Creativity — which is oscillation, rupture, disparate prospectives — can be comprehended only starting from a synthetic conglomeration of convolution which explains the sparse attention from analytic philosophy toward the creative potential of the human.   Mathematical creativity, like artistic creativity, is none other than incessant convolution.  The invention of Galois groups revolves around the obstructions obtained from the local analysis of [integral] equations; Galois urged literally a “metaphysics” of equations.  Riemann surfaces revolve around the problem of the multivalence of certain complex functions and permitted structurally including the Multiple into the One.  The “rising tide” of Grothendieck covers an analytically incomprehensible object mediating a category of cycles [circoli] that permit understanding it (the object) synthetically with respect to its ambient.  In many cases, only a synthetic vision, thanks to sophisticated network of cycles, permits an advance in mathematics.

The situation, therefore, obviously swings back and forth between the analytic and synthetic prospectives.   The work of future generations of philosophers is immense.  First, one needs to get rid of [sbarazzarsi] analytic obfuscation and expose the other side of the balance; at times this other side was denoted “Continental Philosophy,” but it’s worthwhile now to re-order the panorama in a more precise mode (systemic and systematic), introducing the terminology Analytic Philosophy / Synthetic Philosophy.  Second, one needs to construct the body of synthetic doctrine in a very ample way, putting in play great architects (Peirce, late Whitehead, Cassirer, Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze, etc.) and great critics (Warburg, Florenskij, Benjamin, Batjin, Blumenberg, etc.) who have addressed reasoning as territory of frontiers and passages [transiti].  Third, one needs to re-construct culture as infinite fragmentation of an alternative tertiary, a network of residues and traversals [traversi], like places in incessant exchange (Serres).  In a word, one must rewrite, 200 years later, the Quaderno generale of Novalis, grand precursor of which is TRANS, thanks to the infinite variety of passages which appeared in the 19c and 20c.

The object of Synthetic Philosophy (as Continental Philosophy understood it at least in part) must confront many fragments of knowledge that Analytic Philosophy considered as intractable: contradictions, blind points, vague borders, obscure foundations of truth, imprecise shadows where creativity explodes, aesethetic potentiality, etc.  Metaphysics, far from dead, has never been so alive, thanks to the horror generated by those who would kill it.  The great profundities of Greek philosophy, the intractable dimensions of a Lullo or a Leibniz, resurrected untamed.  In the star of Grothendieck contemporary mathematics discovers the multitude of archetypes unthinkable a few decades ago (classifying topoi, motives, Zilber or Gromov groups, Simpson’s inverse mathemtatics, etc.).  In the star of Weinberg, contemporary cosmology is capable of discovering the structural archetypes of the origin of the universe.   In the star of Petitot contemporary neurogeometry discovers the neuronal archetypes that could permit the naturalization of phenomenology.  In the star of Kiefer, contemporary art encounters the archetypes of destruction and beauty according to the zigzagging cycles of civilization.   Everything tends to show that form (the beginning of the 20c), structure (the middle of the 20c) and process (the beginning of the 21c) are much more important than the linguistic and logical turns proposed as the only reason by the analyticists.

As Benjamin said in “Passages” of Paris, we must reawaken.




NOTES

His work:

Fernando Zalamea’s most important work is Synthetic Philosophy of Contemporary Mathematics, Urbanomic London 2012, in which the lovers of mathematics and philosophy can find a profound reconstruction of 20c mathematics.  The italics in the article are the author’s.

Zalamea, a “global mind” who redescribes philosophy with mathematics
Giovanni Maddalena

The encounter with Fernando Zalamea is always an event: mathematician with extremely vast knowledge, philosophy, art critic, writer, essayist, a man of culture in all fields, citizen of Rome, Barcelona, Paris, Boston, and above all, of his beloved Bogotà, where he teaches Mathematics at the National University, Zalamea is true universal thinker.  A recently announced book of Gianluigi Ricuperati, indicated via a complex algorithm the 100 global minds, the most influential in the world.  (“100 Global Minds,”  Roads Publishing.  Above all, Zalamea was more than any [colpisce piu ancora] the master.   When he affably encounters students and young researchers, Zalamea listens, directs, urges always through pertinent notes that valorize that which they propose.  Zalamea inserts each’s studies in a painting that is so vast and with a perspective so ample that each can find his own work in philosophy different from that which it / he would propose to start from “real” mathematics.  One can glimpse a slice of this immense cultural panorama in the small essay, a miniature polemical pamphlet, that Zalamea has written exclusively for Il Foglio.

The idea is simple.  World philosophy is certified [attestato] and blocked in an analytic that rests its foundations on mathematical understandings tied to programs already superceded wtih Gödel (1932) and crystallized in a scientistic and naturalistic version that has little to do with [che poco ha a vedere] the development of mathematics and of science of the last 80 years.   Also, in his present writing, Zalamea contests the importance of some strongholds of this project.

The critique of analytic philosophy has often been carried by the traditional continental philosophy (hermeneutics, phenomenolgy, etc.).  Critiques, above all, always seem naive and external, conducted by thoughts that appear to escape a strict logical confrontation.   The idea of Zalamea, instead, is to criticize analytic starting from logic, and re-establish continental philosophy on the basis of the experience of real mathematics, pardoxically closer to the study of phenomenology, semiotics, aesthetics and hermeneutics than that of analytic development.   In this sense, it is no longer geography (continentale) that counts but the type of reasoning (synthetic) that for now is entirely unexplored, except for the works of a few great precursors like Peirce and Florenskij.

With his proposal, Zalamea contests in fact the distinction between the sciences of nature and the sciences pf the spirit, and more profoundly, impregnated with Kantian knowledge, re-inserts metaphyics in the rational compass.  I also think that the synthetic perspective will entirely depart from the Kantian schema, as I have tried to do with the theory of gesture, which is also the fruit of continuous dialogue with Fernando Zalamea.  I hope that this article helps put into discussion a cultural framework heretofore dated and impoverished.
[ Translated by Sha Xin Wei ]

Sarah Choukah : Gilbert Simondon and Bio-Hacking

Sarah Choukah, a genial and brilliant PhD student from Université de Montréal who participated in a TML grad seminar on capitalist sorcery, did a charming intro to bio-hacking using some Simondonian concepts:


Please consider joining our faculty - grad reading group next semester Wednesdays 4-6 pm at my place, where we’ll read and discuss Simondon’s Mode of Existence of Technical Objects.   We’ll work in English samizdat but welcome those who can help us work with the French original.

RSVP,
Xin Wei

ECS: weather models CM1 and WRF

Hi Brandon, & Julian, Josh, Connor,

This reference from Dr. Melissa Bukovsky, our friend at NCAR should be useful.  I’d like us to understand  the models inside professional grade weather models CM1 and WRF.    

Brandon, can you and Julian please estimate the work / benefit of either plugging those engines into our media system, or implementing some toy version?   Do chat with Connor because he may have peeked at the CM1 refs last summer.   (Kudos Connor)

Rather than reinvent the wheel we should take seriously Melissa’s recommendation re CM1: “This model is designed for idealized studies, unlike others I work with, so its code is much simpler and it will run much more efficiently.  It can also be used with different equation sets.”

What I’ve learned from doing scientific simulations for multiple audiences is that the smartest approach is not to make toy models (like NetLogo) motivated by “education” or “public communications”  bc that burns up infinite amounts of engineering labor for CS lab “demos” rather than effective pedagogy or credible science.  

A more effective and rewarding way to invest our engineering expertise and labor is to take a professional grade system and mask its content or features appropriately to fit the user.  The weather modellers already do something like this — they call it idealization.

Brandon, Josh:

There’s a very strong tendency among computer scientists to make toy models of math and science that satisfy us coders but don’t engage real science or science education.  Instead, I want us to do more professional software engineering, engineering with more anthropological tact and sociological acuity.

At Stanford, with a worldwide net of simulations researchers and teachers, we did this “masking" with a large range of Mathematica modules, from pharma physiology, geophysics, ODE’s, to elementary differential geometry and cosmology to good effect.    It is no more labor, and often actually less software engineering.  More brain (reading other people’s science in papers and textbooks)  and less brawn (coding from scratch based only on images output from other people).   What we did was to code or acquire code that did computations used by professionals in the field, be it physics, maths, medicine, or econometrics, and carefully make student versions by encapsulation, masking, thinning, scaffolding with multimedia narrative etc.     This way instead of infantlizing we give them a headroom.  This way, the software environment can support their learning and growing to whatever extent they can, all the way to the top of the field’s practice.

The analogy would be giving an apprentice cabinet maker real hammers and nails to work with real wood, rather than plastic toy hammers and sponge.

Also, coding everything yourself from scratch is a typical novice programmer’s approach to the world, but software programmers with real world experience learn to reuse other people’s work.  (With proper permission and attribution. :)

Live long and prosper,
Xin Wei


Begin forwarded message:

From: Melissa Bukovsky <bukovsky@ucar.edu>
Subject: Intel/NSF grant and modeling resources
Date: February 5, 2015 at 4:23:30 PM MST
To: Xin Wei Sha <Xinwei.Sha@asu.edu>, Christopher Roberts <cmrober2@asu.edu>

Hi Xin Wei and Chris,

Second, I had a brief discussion with a colleague here (George Bryan) about which numerical weather prediction/climate model it would be best to start with, and I've come up with a good option. It's his model (I knew it existed, I just needed to know more about it before suggesting it).  This model is designed for idealized studies, unlike others I work with, so its code is much simpler and it will run much more efficiently.  It can also be used with different equation sets.  I think it would be perfect for expanding your current system to 3-dimensions while adding atmospheric variables (temperature, moisture, etc.).  It has mostly been used for idealized thunderstorm studies too, which is perfect.  It's webpage is here in case you'd like to see more about it (the code is also there): http://www2.mmm.ucar.edu/people/bryan/cm1/

Third, I found a few good educational modules for learning about weather/climate modeling, if you are still interested in them...

An introduction to climate models: https://www.meted.ucar.edu/nwp/climate_models/index.htm
Modeling fundamentals: https://www.meted.ucar.edu/nwp/model_fundamentals/index.htm
This one is much more complex, but has some good (if old) visualizations in it.  It's about a specific type of thunderstorm system called a Mesoscale Convective System (MCS).  These are an important part of the monsoon system. https://www.meted.ucar.edu/convectn/mcs/mcsweb/mcsframe.htm

I look forward to talking tomorrow afternoon.

Cheers,
Melissa

misinterpretation of brain measurement due to modularity thesis

Thanks to Brenda McCaffrey (AME PhD):

(1) stimulating one part of the brain to induce certain behaviours might cause other, unrelated parts to fire simultaneously, and so make it seem as if these circuits are also involved in the behaviour.

(2). although techniques such as optogenetics may show that a circuit can perform a function, they do not necessarily show that it normally performs that function.

... 

AME research and graduate proseminar: the problem with explaining things in terms of "'parts' of the brain"

Hardcastle and Stewart succinctly point out a fundamental problem at the heart of the methodology of neuroscience (and of cognitive science): the modularity thesis.

Neuroscience did not “discover” modules — loci of functions —  in brains.   Rather “they don’t even have a good way of accessing the appropriate evidence. It is a bias in neuroscience to localize and modularize brain functions.”

The problem with scientistic methodology is that you see what you expect to see.



There’s much more in play: Noah Brender’s work questions the modularity thesis underlying much of technoscience. 
However, another world is possible :)

Xin Wei

demo of rhythm insfruments

Hi Gabby and Garrett , Great — let’s see what you’ve got !

Let me know when you’re around separately or together.   Todd and I are looking forward to see this.  I’ll see if I can swing by before Thurs.


PS Kristi — please feel welcome to chat w faculty and grads affiliated with these core SC projects to get to know what’s happening — you can play with what’s built, and break them.  If you provide insight it’s called research.  :)

On Nov 16, 2015, at 11:22 PM, Garrett Laroy Johnson <gljohns6@asu.edu> wrote:


Hi Xin Wei,

Unfortunately both Gabby and I have class tomorrow at nine thirty AM, but we are both interested in demoing some of our ongoing rhythm work (gabby with footfall, me with speech) 
With you soon. We are aiming to have the rhythm station set up and demoing by Thursday, but will be in tomorrow and Wednesday as well if you fancy checking in sooner. 


Garrett Laroy Johnson 

On Nov 16, 2015, at 12:48, Xin Wei Sha <Xinwei.Sha@asu.edu> wrote:

Dear Tech Team + colleague faculty involved with Walton visit,


I could come to Stauffer at 9:30 tomorrow to check in Tech Team and faculty involved with the Walton visit.
I’d like to share and review the script that I’d like to supply the Dean for approval.

• Stauffer Flex spaces: DC Undergrad Diversity and creativity, refined by studio critique, scaled up
(Loren and David)
Student projects from studio courses
High school through professional post-grad

• Stauffer Lounge: Design for everyday life
Byron curation, overall works
it would be good to take some photos of this space working 
 for when I assemble the updated detailed script for Dean Tepper  tonite

• Matthews iStage: Fusion Art - Science
Chris Roberts overall curation, Pete Technical Direction
Art: Serra instruments sound and video (Todd, Julian)
Science: Experiential Climate Models (Josh, Connor, … )

Thanks all!
Xin Wei